{"id":858,"date":"2014-08-02T15:16:20","date_gmt":"2014-08-02T13:16:20","guid":{"rendered":"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/?p=858"},"modified":"2024-02-24T11:18:37","modified_gmt":"2024-02-24T10:18:37","slug":"perspectives-on-cultural-evolution-by-daniel-c-dennett","status":"publish","type":"post","link":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/webinars\/sfi-cultural-evolution-workshop\/perspectives-on-cultural-evolution-by-daniel-c-dennett\/","title":{"rendered":"Perspectives on Cultural Evolution, by Daniel C. Dennett"},"content":{"rendered":"
These are Daniel Dennett’s introductory remarks on the workshop on cultural evolution he conveyed in Santa Fe in May 2014.<\/p>\n
(Footnotes contain comments by Richerson and Sperber.)<\/p>\n
***
\nEver since Darwin\u2019s Descent of Man (1871), the idea of adopting an evolutionary perspective on human culture has seemed to many to be a natural move, obviously worth trying\u2014and to many others to be a dangerous, \u201cnihilistic,\u201d \u201creductionistic\u201d, \u201cscientistic,\u201d assault on everything we hold dear. Work on cultural evolution has been making good progress in recent years, but has been hindered by distortions, some perhaps deliberate, but others are misunderstandings that naturally arise between slightly different traditions. I formed this working party to try to find common ground and resolve differences among some of the leading theorists and experimentalists. The ten participants included the trio of Boyd, Henrich and Richerson (BRH), a French trio of Sperber, Claidi\u00e8re and Morin (SCM), the memeticists Blackmore and myself, and two philosophers of biology who have been particularly engaged with issues of cultural evolution, Peter Godfrey Smith and Kim Sterelny. Several other leading figures were invited but could not participate for various reasons.<\/p>\n
Each participant was invited to send in two or three recent papers or chapters for everyone to read in advance, and then the first three days were devoted to the \u201cX on Y sessions\u201d, in which each participant (X) in turn took on the task of briefly introducing the work of another participant (Y). I invited all to send me their preferred list of people to introduce, and more or less optimized the pairings to make sure each X-Y pair were drawn from different traditions and no two introduced each other\u2019s work. After fifteen or twenty minutes introduction, each Y then had a chance to respond, followed by general discussion. The atmosphere was informal, permitting frequent interruptions for questions and comments.<\/p>\n
Before the working group convened there was some skepticism and grumbling about the X on Y obligation from various participants, but everybody graciously acceded to my request and the results, in my opinion, confirmed the value of the practice. After the workshop all participants submitted a brief summary of the week, citing what was learned, what was agreed upon, and issues still unresolved. Quoting a few comments from participants: Peter Richerson: \u201cI do think that the disagreements among the various \u2018schools\u2019 of cultural evolution represented at the meeting are relatively modest.\u201d Peter Godfrey Smith: \u201cI think that a lot of progress was made on clarifying disagreements, even where the remaining disagreements remain genuine. . . . It\u2019s progress when an initially cloudy situation gives way to a sharper and more definite set of empiricial uncertainties.\u201d Dan Sperber: \u201cIt has been a wonderful workshop of serious, demanding, insightful, informal, friendly discussion of a kind and quality rarely experienced.\u201d Nicholas Claidi\u00e8re noted that part of the distortion is generated by the way we tend to talk about our work to people outside the field, giving the (wrong) impression that there are schools of thought at war with each other: \u201cGiven the amount of agreement that we have seen during this meeting, I think it would be more productive to present ourselves as having a common goal with diverging interests rather than competing views of the same phenomena.\u201d<\/p>\n
Terminological headaches.<\/p>\n
Three frustrating terminological problems were exposed, but we didn\u2019t resolve how to correct them: \u201ccultural group selection,\u201d \u201cmeme,\u201d and \u201cDarwinian\u201d are all good terms, historically justifiable and useful in context, but by now all are so burdened with legacies of ideological conflict that any use of them invites misbegotten \u201crefutation\u201d or dismissal. Should we abandon the terms in favor of emotionally inert replacements, or should we persist with them, always accompanying their use with a wreath of explanation? These are questions of diplomacy or pedagogical policy, not serious theoretical issues, but still, alas, unignorable.<\/p>\n
As Boyd explained, the adoption by BRH of the term \u201ccultural group selection\u201d had its roots in the relatively uncontroversial theoretical terrain of Sewall Wright\u2019s population genetics (and shifting balance theory), not in later, more dubious and controversial variants. But this is hard to explain to people who have already taken sides for or against \u201cgroup selection\u201d as an important phenomenon in evolution. In any event, the working group, enlightened about what BRH mean\u2014and don\u2019t mean\u2014by cultural group selection, while still harboring somewhat different hunches about its importance, acknowledged that Steve Pinker\u2019s recent \u201cextreme and dismissive\u201d (Henrich) position on Edge.org did not find a target in the work of BRH.<\/p>\n
The popular hijacking of Dawkins\u2019 term \u201cmeme\u201d for any cultural item that \u201cgoes viral\u201d on the Internet, regardless of whether it was intelligently designed or evolved by imitation and natural selection, has been seen by some to subvert the theoretical utility of the term altogether. There is also the unreasoned antipathy the term evokes in many quarters (reminiscent of the antipathy towards the term \u201csociobiology\u201d that led to its abandonment). Alternatively, if one is \u201cDarwinian about Darwinism\u201d we should expect the existence of cultural items that are merely \u201cmemish\u201d to one degree or another, and we might as well go on using the term \u201cmeme\u201d to refer to any relatively well-individuated culturally transmitted item that can serve as a building block or trackable element of culture however it arrives on the scene. Other terms, such as Boyd and Richerson\u2019s \u201ccultural variant\u201d, have been proposed, but the term \u201cmeme\u201d has become so familiar in popular culture that whatever alternative is used will be immediately compared to, identified with, assimilated to meme(a Sperberian attractor, apparently), so perhaps the least arduous course is to adopt the term, leaving open its theoretical definition, in much the way the term \u201cgene\u201d has lost its strict definition as protein-recipe in many quarters. Since the long-term fate of such an item will be settled by differential reproduction (or something similar to differential reproduction) however much insight or \u201cimprovisational intelligence\u201d went into its birth, it has a kind of Darwinian fitness.<\/p>\n
But should we go on talking about whether or not a phenomenon is \u201cDarwinian\u201d? Some think the term gets in the way, since we are seldom if ever alluding to what Darwin himself thought, but rather to the neo-Darwinian, post-DNA synthesis, itself an evolving landmark. On the other hand, there is general agreement within the group that some important elements of human culture evolve by processes strongly analogous to genetic natural selection, and the variations in these processes can be usefully diagrammed using Peter Godfrey Smith\u2019s \u201cDarwinian spaces\u201d (See figure 1 for an instance), in which the similarities and differences can be arrayed in three dimensions. Since, moreover, there is agreement that these cultural regularities can set selection pressures (e.g., a \u201ccultural niche\u201d) for co-evolutionary processes, generating genetic responses (such as adult lactose tolerance), a unified evolutionary perspective, in which the trade-offs between cultural and genetic evolution can be plotted, is a valuable organizer of phenomena, some \u201cmore Darwinian\u201d than others. No other term suggests itself for the set of features that mark paradigmatic (neo-)Darwinian phenomena, so perhaps the misunderstandings the term tends to generate can be deflected.<\/p>\n
Figure 1:<\/p>\n