{"id":7124,"date":"2018-03-08T13:44:23","date_gmt":"2018-03-08T12:44:23","guid":{"rendered":"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/?p=7124"},"modified":"2023-07-24T16:28:09","modified_gmt":"2023-07-24T14:28:09","slug":"rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation","status":"publish","type":"post","link":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/blogs\/dan-sperber\/rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation\/","title":{"rendered":"Rethinking ostension: (2) Attention manipulation"},"content":{"rendered":"

I believe we relevance theorists missed something important in considering ostension only in the context of what we called ostensive-inferential communication. Ostension, I want to suggest, is more diverse and widespread.<\/p>\n

In relevance theory, we have been contrasting two mechanisms of communication, coded communication, also commonly known as \u201csignalling,\u201d and what I will, for the time being, call \u201cO-I communication\u201d (O-I for \u201costensive-inferential\u201d or \u201costensive-interpretive\u201d \u2013 I hope we soon find a better solution to the terminological problem I raised in the first post<\/a> of this series). Unlike coded communication or signalling, which we took in agreement with the relevant literature to be the standard form of animal communication, we argued that O-I communication is a recent adaptation relying on typically human mindreading abilities. We underscored the discontinuities between these two forms of communication: it is a mistake to look for precursor forms of human O-I communication in animal and in particular in non-human primate signalling (as argued in detail by Thom Scott-Phillips in Speaking our Minds<\/em>\u00a0[1]).<\/p>\n

Ah but there is a third form of communication (in a very broad sense of \u201ccommunication\u201d), a very ancient and very widespread one: attention manipulation! (Arguably attention manipulation is itself a special case of an even wider category: sensory manipulation; sensory manipulation doesn\u2019t necessarily need the attention of the target; however, here I focus on attention manipulation). Attention manipulation itself takes many forms. Ostension, I will argue (in the next post) is a recent form of attention manipulation.<\/p>\n

Today\u2019s post is about forms of attention manipulation older than ostension proper. But to begin with, what is attention, and how might it be advantageous to manipulate the attention of others? Attention has been intensively studied in psychology and more recently, in neuropsychology, with competing models and approaches. Judging from my limited acquaintance with this vast literature, the idea that attention aims at selecting the most relevant inputs is a commonplace. I have not, however, come across a worked-out definition of relevance in this literature, let alone a shared one. What one encounters, rather, are common sense examples: inputs that are evidence of potential reward or danger, inputs that may contribute to the agent\u2019s goals are typically relevant and worth processing. True, no doubt. In the next posts, I will argue for a more precise notion of relevance and show how it matters to a better understanding of ostension, but here such a vague and intuitive notion of relevance will do.<\/p>\n

So, back half a billion years ago. During the Cambrian explosion, animal cognitive mechanisms became complex to the point where selection of the most relevant inputs became a precondition for efficient cognition and attention mechanisms evolved. When attention first appeared, nothing had yet evolved to manipulate it. Nothing in what animals could attend to in their environment was designed to attract (or evade) their attention. However, organisms stand to benefit or suffer from the behaviour of other organisms, which may be partly determined by attention mechanisms. Hence, once attention-capable organisms evolved, ways to take advantage of their attention and its behavioural effects (or not to suffer from them) evolved in turn. In many species, for instance, the chances of mating are greater if you can attract the attention of potential mates. Cross-species mutualism (say between cleaner fish and their bigger fish clients) often requires attracting the attention of potential partners. And so on.<\/p>\n

(Camouflage, used by many prey and predators, is not a means to attract or distract the attention of the other, but to escape it altogether. Sure, it is an adaptation to the risks presented by others’ attention, but still, it may be better not to categorise it as a manipulation of attention proper, nor as a form of communication.)<\/p>\n

Evolved means to attract the attention of others need not involve any intentional behaviour, or, for that matter any behaviour at all. After all, plants have no intentions but still, many do produce flowers the function of which is to attract the attention of potential pollinators. In many animals, changes of colour, which is generally not something the animal can intend, have evolved to attract the attention of potential mates: the belly of male three-spined stickleback fish, for instance, turns red at the time of breeding, attracting females (and also, sometimes, the aggression of other males, as famously demonstrated by Niko Tinbergen).<\/p>\n

Manipulation of the attention of one animal by another is typically an adaptive behaviour. It performs its function by influencing the targeted animal\u2019s cognitive states and behaviour in a way that is advantageous to the manipulator. The highly salient red belly of male sticklebacks contributes, by attracting the attention of females and thereby influencing their behaviour, to the reproductive success of males.<\/p>\n

Manipulation of attention (or sensory manipulation more generally) is a form of communication in a very broad sense of the term, where communication consists in one organism influencing others by modifying their cognitive states. Often in evolutionary and comparative studies of animals, communication is defined more narrowly as co-extensive with signalling. Signalling itself is defined as an interaction where not only does the communicator produce a signal the function of which is to influence a receiver, but where the receiver decodes the signal and produces a reaction adapted to it. \u00a0For signalling systems to evolve, two conditions must be fulfilled: producing a signal has to be advantageous to communicators; reacting appropriately to the signal has to be advantageous to receivers (see David Harper and John Maynard Smith\u2019s 2003 book, Animals signals<\/em>, and Thom Scott Phillips’s discussion of the issue [2]).<\/p>\n

The male sticklebacks\u2019 red belly is both a way to attract the attention of females and a signal to these females. Female sticklebacks\u2019 reproductive success benefits from paying attention to the red belly of males ready to breed (not just its presence, but also its intensity, see ), and from reacting appropriately.<\/p>\n

Similarly, many flowering plants in need of pollination attract insects by advertising themselves as a source of valuable nectar. The bright colours and subtle scents of their flowers signal the presence of nectar. In visiting flowers and unwittingly carrying some pollen from male stamina to female pistils, pollinators, for their part, help the plants reproduce: the insects\u2019 reaction to the signal is advantageous both to the insect and to the plant.<\/p>\n

\"\"<\/a>
\nAll naturally evolved flowers have the function of attracting pollinators, but not all of them do so by means of signalling. Some species of orchids, for instance, mimic the shape, colour and odour of a female wasp, tricking male wasps to try and copulate with them (see [3]). In the process, some pollen gets stuck on the wasps, who carry it to another orchid that, again, they mistake for a potential mate. The wasps, in other words, are being tricked into acting as pollinators. From an evolutionary and functional point of view, orchids and wasps are in quite different predicaments. The orchids have evolved to influence wasps by providing them with misleading cues. These cues\u2014the shape, colour and odour of the flower\u2014are adaptations that are quite successful at performing their function. The cognitive mechanisms male wasps use when picking up these cues have evolved to detect genuine female wasps, not orchid mimics. Hence, in being activated by orchid mimicry, the male wasps’ female detector malfunctions. When a cue is an evolved adaptation for the organism that produces it\u2014for instance an orchid\u2014aimed at influencing the behaviour of an animal\u2014for instance a male wasp\u2014by causing some of its cognitive mechanisms to malfunction, this is a clear case of attention manipulation, but not of signalling.<\/p>\n

As illustrated by the example of the deceptive orchids (or by the famous case of females birds such as killdeers feigning to have a broken wing in order to attract a predator away from their nest), manipulation of attention is a form of communication that need not involve signalling proper.<\/p>\n

Conversely, signalling can be effective without attracting the attention of the receivers. Quite complex pheromone signalling has been demonstrated among Caenorhabditis elegans<\/em> roundworms, even though, with their few hundred neurons, they don\u2019t do attention (see [4]). <\/em><\/p>\n

Among humans, Iren\u00e4us Eibl-Eibesfeldt demonstrated in a 1968 article [5] the existence of a universal signal: when recognizing a friend at a distance, humans typically raise their eyebrows for a fraction of a second: mutual awareness is thereby achieved but the signal itself \u2013 the \u201ceyebrow flash\u201d \u2013 is produced and decoded unconsciously. Or to take an example closer to home, Guillaume Dezecache et al. demonstrated in a 2013 article [6] the existence of unconscious signals of emotion, which help explain emotional contagion in crowds.<\/p>\n

All this to argue that attention manipulation 1) is an ancient and widespread form of communication; 2) is quite distinct from signalling: it can work without involving signals just as signalling can work without involving attention.<\/p>\n

One last point: this post (unlike the previous one) is not about terminology. It is about substantive distinctions and claims. In particular, if you don\u2019t like my broad use of the term \u201ccommunication\u201d to include attention manipulation, replace it with \u201ccommunication*\u201d or whatever term you prefer. Same thing if you don\u2019t like \u201cattention manipulation,\u201d and so forth.<\/p>\n

In the next post of this series, I will suggest that ostension is a form of attention manipulation that involves a modicum of mindreading (but much less than full-fledged O-I communication). (Juan-Carlos Gomez, by the way, has long been advocating such an idea).<\/p>\n


\n[1] Scott-Phillips, T. (2014).\u00a0Speaking our minds: Why human communication is different, and how language evolved to make it special<\/i>. Bloomsbury Publishing.<\/p>\n[2] Defining biological communication<\/a><\/p>\n[3] Gaskett, A. C. (2011). Orchid pollination by sexual deception: pollinator perspectives.\u00a0Biological Reviews<\/i>,\u00a086<\/i>(1), 33-75.<\/p>\n[4] Reimagining pheromone signalling in the model nematode Caenorhabditis elegans<\/a><\/p>\n[5] Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1968). Zur Ethologie des menschlichen Gru\u00dfverhaltens: I. Beobachtungen an Balinesen, Papuas und Samoanern nebst vergleichenden Bemerkungen. Zeitschrift f\u00fcr Tierpsychologie<\/i>,\u00a025<\/i>(6), 727-744.<\/p>\n[6] Evidence for Unintentional Emotional Contagion Beyond Dyads<\/a><\/p>\n","protected":false},"excerpt":{"rendered":"

I believe we relevance theorists missed something important in considering ostension only in the context of what we called ostensive-inferential communication. Ostension, I want to suggest, is more diverse and widespread. In relevance theory, we have been contrasting two mechanisms of communication, coded communication, also commonly known as \u201csignalling,\u201d and what I will, for the […]<\/p>\n","protected":false},"author":677,"featured_media":7132,"comment_status":"open","ping_status":"closed","sticky":false,"template":"","format":"standard","meta":{"footnotes":""},"categories":[5],"tags":[],"acf":[],"yoast_head":"\nRethinking ostension: (2) Attention manipulation - International Cognition and Culture Institute<\/title>\n<meta name=\"robots\" content=\"index, follow, max-snippet:-1, max-image-preview:large, max-video-preview:-1\" \/>\n<link rel=\"canonical\" href=\"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/blogs\/dan-sperber\/rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation\/\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:locale\" content=\"en_GB\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:type\" content=\"article\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:title\" content=\"Rethinking ostension: (2) Attention manipulation - International Cognition and Culture Institute\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:description\" content=\"I believe we relevance theorists missed something important in considering ostension only in the context of what we called ostensive-inferential communication. Ostension, I want to suggest, is more diverse and widespread. In relevance theory, we have been contrasting two mechanisms of communication, coded communication, also commonly known as \u201csignalling,\u201d and what I will, for the […]\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:url\" content=\"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/blogs\/dan-sperber\/rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation\/\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:site_name\" content=\"International Cognition and Culture Institute\" \/>\n<meta property=\"article:published_time\" content=\"2018-03-08T12:44:23+00:00\" \/>\n<meta property=\"article:modified_time\" content=\"2023-07-24T14:28:09+00:00\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:image\" content=\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-content\/uploads\/orchidwasp.jpg\" \/>\n\t<meta property=\"og:image:width\" content=\"734\" \/>\n\t<meta property=\"og:image:height\" content=\"588\" \/>\n<meta name=\"twitter:card\" content=\"summary\" \/>\n<meta name=\"twitter:creator\" content=\"@dzfsqsd\" \/>\n<meta name=\"twitter:label1\" content=\"Written by\">\n\t<meta name=\"twitter:data1\" content=\"Dan Sperber\">\n\t<meta name=\"twitter:label2\" content=\"Estimated reading time\">\n\t<meta name=\"twitter:data2\" content=\"7 minutes\">\n<script type=\"application\/ld+json\" class=\"yoast-schema-graph\">{\"@context\":\"https:\/\/schema.org\",\"@graph\":[{\"@type\":\"WebSite\",\"@id\":\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/#website\",\"url\":\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/\",\"name\":\"International Cognition and Culture Institute\",\"description\":\"\",\"potentialAction\":[{\"@type\":\"SearchAction\",\"target\":\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/?s={search_term_string}\",\"query-input\":\"required name=search_term_string\"}],\"inLanguage\":\"en-GB\"},{\"@type\":\"ImageObject\",\"@id\":\"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/blogs\/dan-sperber\/rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation\/#primaryimage\",\"inLanguage\":\"en-GB\",\"url\":\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-content\/uploads\/orchidwasp.jpg\",\"width\":734,\"height\":588},{\"@type\":\"WebPage\",\"@id\":\"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/blogs\/dan-sperber\/rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation\/#webpage\",\"url\":\"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/blogs\/dan-sperber\/rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation\/\",\"name\":\"Rethinking ostension: (2) Attention manipulation - International Cognition and Culture Institute\",\"isPartOf\":{\"@id\":\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/#website\"},\"primaryImageOfPage\":{\"@id\":\"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/blogs\/dan-sperber\/rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation\/#primaryimage\"},\"datePublished\":\"2018-03-08T12:44:23+00:00\",\"dateModified\":\"2023-07-24T14:28:09+00:00\",\"author\":{\"@id\":\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/#\/schema\/person\/6d6c8fd5968dd89eb28b9a6bd5e500a9\"},\"inLanguage\":\"en-GB\",\"potentialAction\":[{\"@type\":\"ReadAction\",\"target\":[\"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/blogs\/dan-sperber\/rethinking-ostension-2-attention-manipulation\/\"]}]},{\"@type\":\"Person\",\"@id\":\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/#\/schema\/person\/6d6c8fd5968dd89eb28b9a6bd5e500a9\",\"name\":\"Dan Sperber\",\"image\":{\"@type\":\"ImageObject\",\"@id\":\"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/#personlogo\",\"inLanguage\":\"en-GB\",\"url\":\"http:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-content\/uploads\/dan-96x96.jpg\",\"caption\":\"Dan Sperber\"},\"description\":\"description\",\"sameAs\":[\"http:\/\/www.dan.sperber.fr\",\"https:\/\/twitter.com\/dzfsqsd\"]}]}<\/script>\n<!-- \/ Yoast SEO plugin. -->","_links":{"self":[{"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/7124"}],"collection":[{"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts"}],"about":[{"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/types\/post"}],"author":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/users\/677"}],"replies":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/comments?post=7124"}],"version-history":[{"count":6,"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/7124\/revisions"}],"predecessor-version":[{"id":17452,"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/7124\/revisions\/17452"}],"wp:featuredmedia":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/media\/7132"}],"wp:attachment":[{"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/media?parent=7124"}],"wp:term":[{"taxonomy":"category","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/categories?post=7124"},{"taxonomy":"post_tag","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/cognitionandculture.local\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/tags?post=7124"}],"curies":[{"name":"wp","href":"https:\/\/api.w.org\/{rel}","templated":true}]}}