De l’origine des fables<\/a>. Despite what I just said, I would disagree slightly with Horton, at least in emphasis, on the reason most cultures use what he calls the \u201cpersonal idiom\u201d \u2014 gods and spirits \u2014 in their theories. My own take on it will follow right below. Fontenelle, however, gets the emphasis right in my opinion; and otherwise his account, while less elaborate (he devotes only about one page to this), is remarkably similar to Horton\u2019s: gods are explanations of the world by analogy, the results of a \u201cprinciple so natural that even today our philosophy has none other\u201d (English translation, quoted by Guthrie on p. 21). It would be quite astonishing if it were to turn out that the possibly oldest treatment of the topic hits the mark best, notwithstanding all the later discussions through the centuries.<\/p>\nSo where does the personal idiom come from?<\/p>\n
(The rest of this post is copied verbatim, except for a few omissions, from the original note.)<\/p>\n
Dunning calls the environment out on the \u201cincomplete or misleading data\u201d it provides. I would put it in our case as follows. The agentive interpretation, attributing desires and other mental states, is clearly apt for a lot of events, namely those caused by humans and animals; and one might not even entertain the thought that the environment would mix in other events, such as rain and wind, where this interpretation just can\u2019t work well any more \u2014 however hard one may try to get the mental states right. No desires at all are involved in the weather\u2019s actions, but this is far less clear than that desires are involved when humans and animals act, at least for someone without a specific education or cultural context.<\/p>\n
For an analogy, let\u2019s replace the ability to cause events with something else typical of humans and animals: the tendency to leave footprints. Imagine a world where sometimes, without any agent involvement, shapes appear in the soil that look like footprints (although perhaps much bigger). People inhabiting such a world could surely be forgiven for mistakenly assuming these lookalikes to be footprints, left by agents not unlike themselves or animals.<\/p>\n
They might see through the hoax if given a chance to directly observe a track of footprint-lookalikes coming into existence without anyone in sight. Or they might then instead perceive an invisible agent walking there. But notice that, in our original case in our own world, supposed agents causing weather events need not be invisible outright. A rain god could be merely hidden from view, or too far away to see.<\/p>\n
One might criticise the footprints analogy for relying on one specific sort of shape, out of many possible, when the case at hand involves all sorts of events rather than just a specific sort. Again, then, let\u2019s replace the ability to cause events with something else typical of humans and (less so this time) animals: the ability to create design. All sorts of design, so the criticism doesn\u2019t apply here. Imagine a world where sometimes, without any agent involvement, appears what looks like design \u2026 but this is now reminiscent of our own world! Think of eyes, or birds\u2019 wings. The world exhibits apparent design not created by humans or animals; and unsurprisingly, beliefs in \u201cintelligent design\u201d, in some form or other, have been widespread at all times.<\/p>\n
I should note that Guthrie, on pp. 186\u2013187, invokes his account of anthropomorphism to help explain the human feeling of a designer behind the works of nature, citing Hume on the need for such help. But otherwise it would not have occurred to me that an intellectualist approach might be insufficient to account for the beliefs. Provided, of course, that Darwin\u2019s notion of design by natural selection is not available as a viable alternative to design by agent. Likewise, in our original case the argument depends on there not being any notion of natural event-causation. That is, on Nietzsche being correct when stating “Now man believed originally that wherever he saw something happen, a will had to be at work in the background as a cause, and a personal, willing being. Any notion of mechanics was far from his mind.”<\/p>\n
I read this, originally from The Gay Science, when it appeared last year as the first part of a larger quotation in a post by Cris Campbell on Nietzsche and theory of mind. We should be alert for counterexamples, though. Have certain happenings always been seen as unconnected to agency? That would present a challenge to our parsimonious approach. It would show that people had the option, after all, to cut agency out of the picture, as in today\u2019s mechanistic view of geological or weather events; and yet they didn\u2019t exercise it as often as they \u201cshould\u201d have done. Why not? At this point, to answer that, it may make more sense to invoke, as Guthrie does, a human cognitive bias or feature.<\/p>\n
But do we have to answer it? Does such a counterexample exist? I conclude the post with two caveats regarding what would qualify. First, while I have singled out desires among mental states (cf. Dennett\u2019s concept of intentional stance, singling out beliefs and desires), it is not enough for an event to be not thought of as desired by an agent to happen. Agents may cause events not only on purpose, but also out of carelessness. And as side effects. When there is a new footprint, it is clear that its creation must have been a small event when it happened. But everyone knows, presumably, that most likely this event wasn\u2019t desired by the agent who caused it.<\/p>\n
Secondly, of course all people have concepts of physics. For example, everyone knows gravity. However, even if the downward trajectory of an object is seen as unfolding by the necessity of physics, the perceived cause of the event could still be a (supposed) agent who dropped or hurled the object in the first place. What if it was pushed off a cliff by the impact of another object? That would be physics as well. Yet who set the other object in motion, then? Only examples qualify that lack any perceived contribution from agents with desires and other mental states.<\/p>\n
\n[1] Guthrie, S. E. (1995).\u00a0Faces in the clouds: A new theory of religion<\/i>. Oxford University Press.<\/p>\n[2] Horton, R. (1997).\u00a0Patterns of thought in Africa and the West: Essays on magic, religion and science<\/i>. Cambridge University Press.<\/p>\n","protected":false},"excerpt":{"rendered":" I am pleased to have been given by the ICCI the opportunity to advertise two notes here, each about four pages long, that I have recently written and put on SSRN. Both try to shed light on supernatural agency beliefs. The abstract to the first one reads: Should we account for belief in supernatural agents […]<\/p>\n","protected":false},"author":1218,"featured_media":0,"comment_status":"open","ping_status":"closed","sticky":false,"template":"","format":"standard","meta":{"footnotes":""},"categories":[4],"tags":[],"acf":[],"yoast_head":"\n
Some thoughts on supernatural agency beliefs - International Cognition and Culture Institute<\/title>\n \n \n \n \n \n \n \n \n \n \n \n \n\t \n\t \n\t \n