- 'Speaking Our Minds' Book Club
No communication without reputation, no reputation without communication
I chose to organise an ICCI book club around Speaking Our Minds because it is an exceptional book in more than one way. It ties together two research traditions¬—the pragmatic approach to linguistics and the Darwinian legacy in biology—, that lie at the heart of our field. It does so in a perfect format—the book is a delight to read, and to teach. Yet a good Book Club book should be more than a good book: it should also stir up discussions.
Speaking Our Minds (SOM) is sure to do that: here is a book that claims to solve every major problem linked with the birth of human language! I won’t be the only one who doubts that. I think that Thom Scott-Phillips’ account of how human communication evolved leaves at least one key problem unsolved: How is communication stable in the face of free-riding and deception? In the two sections of SOM that he devotes to that issue (6.5.–6.6), and in his paper On the correct application of animal signalling theory to human communication, Thom rejects the standard solutions to the problem. In the field of language evolution, these tend to come from signalling theory, and to involve the Handicap Principle . With some nuances, I share his grim view of the prospects of signalling theory. Yet his own solution is not just extremely sketchy, at times it verges on circularity.
Words are cheap: The Handicap Principle is a red herring
Let’s start with one thing we all agree on: one family of explanations that work very well for biological signals in general cannot explain the stability of human communication. Here I dwell on Thom’s opposition to Zahavi’s much misused “Handicap Principle”. At the principle’s core is the idea that a signal’s honesty may be stabilized by the costs involved in displaying it. The peacock’s tail, for instance, is a wasteful ornament, so wasteful that the fact of growing it is an indicator of good health. Another popular example (indeed, handicap theory’s poster child) is the springbok’s pronking behaviour. Springboks, it is said, will jump and frolic in front of a predator simply as a way of advertising their athletic capacities: what springbok would be mad enough to nag a lion, unless it is extremely fast?
Thom cites the peacock’s tail, but not the springbok example. I think that is not fortuitous: pronking springboks do not really obey the Handicap Principle as Thom sees it. In his view, the Handicap Principle involves signals that are costly to produce, and that is not the case of pronking. What makes pronking a handicap is its consequence: the risks the animal incurs by frolicking in front of a predator, wasting time and energy that it might need to run for its life. The cost of taking those risks is not paid when producing the pronking signal. It may be paid later when the lionesses chases after the springbok. The costs of pronking, in other words, are deterrents: they are penalties that a springbok would incur if it were signalling dishonestly. They lie in the future. In the peacock’s case, in contrast, the costs are (in large part at least) paid by the peacock when it grows its tail, as a necessary aspect of producing it. In Thom’s view, it seems that a genuine handicap must entail such production costs, and so he reserves the term “handicap” for these. This clarification is one of the book’s most welcome contributions (more on this below).
Conspicuous consumption and the Handicap Principle
Thom (SOM, 6.5) has two points to make against handicap-principle explanations for the evolution of biological signals, when humans are concerned. First, he blames much of the literature for failing to understand that the Handicap Principle requires differential costs: a handicap must be “Free to those who can afford it, very expensive to those who can’t” (SOM, 146). In that vein, Thom criticizes those who construe conspicuous consumption as an instantiation of the Handicap Principle, because conspicuous consumption implies costly purchases, but no differential cost:
"(…) if you can afford to spend money on objects like diamond rings and designer clothes, whose non-signalling functions could be equally well fulfilled by far less expensive purchases, you must be wealthy indeed. (…) However, [this] is not a great example [of the Handicap Principle] because it is not, in fact, a handicap at all. This is because there are no differential costs involved. Put simply, jewellers do not have different prices for different customers (…). Conspicuous consumption is an index of wealth, not a handicap." (SOM, 148)
I beg to differ. Marginal utility theory teaches us that spending ten thousand dollars on a watch is indeed more expensive for us than it is for Bill Gates. The dollar that gets my fortune to grow to one hundred and one dollars is worth more than the one that makes it grow from one million to one million and one. The costs of a one dollar purchase are correspondingly lower for the very rich. Thus, conspicuous consumption is a true handicap: an expensive watch is a purchase that the rich can afford at a lesser opportunity cost than the poor, and it is, of course, causally associated with wealth.
Similar remarks could be made about some other examples mentioned in the book—deer calls, for instance. A deer call’s pitch (or its formants distribution, but I’ll keep things simple) reflects the caller’s size: having a larynx of a given size produces a call with a certain pitch. Using Maynard-Smith and Harper’s terminology, Thom calls this an index, that is to say, a signal that is reliable because it is physiologically impossible to fake it. In Thom’s view, indexes cannot obey the Handicap Principle, because they involve no differential cost (unlike, say, the peacock’s tail). Things are not so obvious to me. First, deep-pitch calls do have a physiological cost (the cost of growing a large body and giving out calls). Second, it is not completely unimaginable that a small deer might grow a big larynx, with terrible consequences for the deer’s viability and fitness. So, rather than being impossible, the low-pitched call is immensely costly for small deers, virtually free for bigger ones. “Free to those who can afford it, very expensive to those who can’t”: the essence of differential cost. In this deer calls are no different from peacocks’ tails.
(At this point, one might reply by citing Maynard-Smith and Harper, for whom a handicap must always include a "strategic cost" in addition to its "efficiency cost". In other words, a cost must be incurred over and above the cost of actually transmitting the relevant piece of information. Yet I think there are reasons to resist this view. First, because it makes little sense of cases like the peacock’s tail: in a way the peacock pays exactly the cost that needs to be paid to advertise its own health—it is not being inefficient. Second, strategic costs jar with the “differential cost” principle—the view that handicaps should be “free to those who can afford it”.)
Knowing a handicap from a deterrent
On the other hand, I fully endorse Thom’s second point against signalling theory. SOM (147–150) does a fantastic job of pointing out the muddles that people fall into when they fail to distinguish handicap costs from deterrents. As Thom points out, handicap costs are “paid by honest signallers (…) as part of the very act of being honest”, while deterrents are “paid by dishonest signallers when they deviate from honesty” (SOM, 148). The distinction matters when discussing evolutionary stability, because handicap-based signals are likely to prove more reliable than the ones whose costs derive from deterrence. The peacock’s tail indicates health simply by virtue of its being there. The springbok’s pronking, in contrast, proves little by itself, when performed in an empty savannah. It is a reliable signal of health only if (i) a predator is present, (ii) that predator is fast and hungry, (iii) the springbok knows this and (iv) the springbok is correct in its prediction that the lion can easily be outrun. If any of these conditions fail to obtain, the deterrents collapse, and so does honesty.
(Thom’s discussion brought back quite a few memories of discussions with handicap aficionados who failed to see this crucial difference. In one such discussion (available online here and here) a group of behavioural ecologists argued that almost everything about diplomacy and international relations is based on the peacock’s tail principle. They refused to see the difference between a nuclear test, which is costly to produce and hence a reliable indicator of military capacity, and a declaration made, say, in front of the United Nations, which might involve unpleasant consequences if one lies, but is nothing costly to utter and thus proves nothing by itself.)
To summarise, I have minor disagreements over two points of interpretation of the Handicap Principle: I think that the Handicap Principle might originally have meant to encompass deterrents (as the popularity of the pronking springbok suggests). I also think that differential costs are nothing special, and because of this I wouldn’t restrict the scope of the Handicap Principle as narrowly as Thom does: Veblen’s conspicuous consumption is a bona fide illustration of the Handicap Principle, and there is nothing deeply wrong in linking natural indexes (like the pitch of deer calls) to handicaps.
More importantly, though, I fully agree with Thom’s main point: the Handicap Principle cannot help us understand the stability of human communication, because its proponents make a muddle of the distinction between handicaps and deterrents. The former kind of cost plays no role at all in making language reliable. Words are cheap—meaning that he cost of uttering them is (i) trivially low and (ii) unrelated to what the words signal. Handicap costs are not what makes human communication reliable. What does, then, must be some kind of deterrent.
Thom’s solution: the reputational costs of deception
Having started on such an excellent footing, Thom’s account essentially stops where it should start. Human communication is kept stable and reliable, in his view, because of the loss of reputation that deception would entail. On this, Thom’s 2008 paper is slightly less elliptic than the book:
"Sufficient conditions for cost-free signalling in which reliability is ensured through deterrents are that signals be verified with relative ease (if they are not verifiable then individuals will not know who is and who is not worthy of future attention) and that costs be incurred when unreliable signalling is revealed. These conditions are fulfilled in the human case: individuals are able to remember the past behaviour of others in sufficient detail to make informed judgements about whether or not to engage in future interactions; and refusal to engage in such interactions produces costs for the excluded individual. (…) Moreover, this process would snowball once off the ground, as individuals would be able to exchange information – gossip – about whether others were reliable communication partners (Enquist & Leimar, 1993); and that exchange would itself be kept reliable by the very same mechanisms." (Scott-Phillips 2008)
This view, I think, takes too much for granted. We would need to know how humans came to have mutually beneficial interactions, on a regular basis, with individuals who could cheat them, but most of the time did not; how humans could reliably verify the validity of other’s signals; how, when a signal seemed inaccurate, one could know that one was the victim of a deceptive informant (as opposed to an incompetent one). Of course, a proper answer to all these questions cannot involve communication, at least not in the first few steps; nor can it appeal to the kind of cooperation that communication makes possible.
From the few lines above it seems that Thom has in mind a scenario involving mechanisms of partner choice. Redouan Bshary’s work on mutualistic cooperation among cleaning fishes (see one example here [1]) could serve as an analogy. These fishes need to coordinate on mutually profitable cleaning operations (removing dead skin, parasites, and such like). They appear to memorise it when one fish has assisted them longer and more efficiently than others in the past: they preferentially choose that fish for future joint ventures. Fishes who fail to cooperate optimally, for instance by giving up cleaning before they are expected to, are gradually pushed away from the pool of desired partners. One thing to say for this scenario is that it does not involve communication in any serious sense: memory of individual encounters, occasionally augmented by eavesdropping, does everything.
Yet our ancestors were not cleaning fishes. I mean that, before the rise of communication, nothing guarantees that they routinely recruited non-relatives for mutually profitable ventures. We cannot be sure, either, that failures to cooperate were visible to the public eye like they are in cleaning fishes. There is a bigger story to be told here, but it is not told in SOM. Suppose, however, that we skip this issue. Suppose that mutually beneficial cooperation and partner choice were well established before our story starts; could they explain the early stability of communication?
I am not sure. For a number of reasons, liars should be much harder to spot than cleaner fishes who free-ride on others’ efforts. Useful communication is about things that are far from us, in space or time. Because of this, communication’s accuracy can seldom be judged here and now, in front of numerous witnesses, like the failings of cleaner fishes. The consequences of a lie for its victims are typically delayed, and difficult to interpret. Suppose I told you that yonder tree is full of juicy apples, but you find out (moments later) that it only carries poisonous manchineel fruits. Can you call me a liar? Not before you make sure that (i) I was being malevolent, not just incompetent, (ii) you yourself are competent enough to tell an apple tree from a manchineel. Even if you succeed at steps (i) and (ii), the fact that I lied to you is not (unlike cheating in cleaning fishes) a public event that people can eavesdrop on. Thus, on the face of it, we should doubt the power of partner choice, individual memory, and eavesdropping, to prevent deception.
A more reliable alternative would be public reputation, established through communication between individuals. Thom clearly has it in mind in several parts of the book (e.g. when he cites Othello’s Cassio); but the circularity of this solution is too obvious to stress. Public reputation is kept reliable by the very acts of communication that it is supposed to police. The messages that make up public reputation can, after all, be just as deceptive as any other kind of communication. They can arguably be even more so, since reputation is often diffuse, informal, and not assignable to one source in particular. If we solve the problem of reliable communication by assuming reliable public reputation, I doubt the buck can ever stop.
Until such questions are addressed, reputation will remain the deus ex machina that intervenes at the end of the play, to tie up the loose ends of the plot. What a good plot, though.
Acknowledgement: I thank Denis Tatone for his precious input on this text.
[1] Bshary, R., & Grutter, A. S. (2005). Punishment and partner switching cause cooperative behaviour in a cleaning mutualism. Biology Letters, 1(4), 396-399.
Hugo Mercier 23 June 2015 (17:32)
Thanks for a very interesting post Olivier.
A detail. I was under the impression that pronking refered to a rather more specific behavior than what you described, namely, simply jumping straight up as high as possible. Such a behavior would then seem to be an index: only a gazelle that has the strength and stamina to jump that high can actually do it. In this case, deterrence would have nothing to do with it.
(Note that even if this were the case, your remarks about the deers would apply: gazelles could presumably evolve that are good at jumping high but crap at running, and it's only the cost of this option, and not its supposed sheer physical impossibility, that would keep things in check).
Is there any evidence either way?
Hugo Mercier 23 June 2015 (17:39)
Another detail. I'm not quite persuaded by your example regarding the supposed difficulty of using reputation as a deterrent to keep communication stable in the early stages of language evolution.
It seems that neither (i) nor (ii) are necessary.
Regarding (i), I don't see why it would be necessary to establish malevolence. If someone has given you information that turns out to be harmful, you trust them less, that's the end of it. That's enough to create an incentive for them to be more careful when communicating.
Regarding (ii), even if you were able to tell the difference, wouldn't you still have a reason to lower the trust you put in the other guy?
And I don't see why a lot of communication wouldn't take place in at least semi public spaces (i.e. the communication would be aimed at one individual, but others would be likely to overhear), and even why this would be necessary: if an individual often provides harmful information, no one will trust him, and his fitness will be substantially reduced, no?
Olivier Morin 23 June 2015 (20:13)
Hi Hugo! Thanks for the comments.
About pronking: Your interpretation is one among a dozen conflicting interpretations of pronking/stotting, and it conflicts with the handicap-principle explanation. Obviously I don't claim to know which interpretation is true, it was just an illustration (I can't tell a springbok from a Thompson gazelle, and everything I know about those I learnt from David Attenborough :o).
About spotting early lies: I raised four problems for Thom's account. It has to explain (1) how mutualism arose, (2) how people tell deceiving informants from incompetent ones, (3) how people know that their informants are more knowledgeable than they themselves are, and (4) how knowledge of deception spreads without communication when opportunities for eavesdropping are limited.
I agree that (2) is not the worst problem. People might ust avoid useless informants, be they incompetent or malevolent, without trying to know which is which. Yet this is a very imperfect solution. Deceptiveness is easily thwarted by mechanisms of partner choice or partner control, but it is hard to see how the same mechanisms would "cure" cluelessness. Uninformed people remain uninformed no matter what: incentives just cannot turn clueless informants into good ones. Responding to clueless informant by avoiding them in the future will be a poor move in many cases (next time, the same clueless informant might possess a precious piece of information, and it won't pay to shun her), whereas shunning deceivers will be the thing to do. In a partner-choice framework, it makes adaptive sense to distinguish mistakes from lies. (Besides, Thom's account is explicitly framed as an account of how communication roots out deceptive misuses—"the boy who cried wolf".)
Concerning (3), I don't really understand your objection. If I'm facing what I think is a manchineel tree, and the informant tells me it's an apple tree, the only way I can truly know who got it right is by eating the fruit—in which case, if I'm right, I'm dead.
Anyway, that still leaves issues (1) and (4)...
Hugo Mercier 23 June 2015 (21:11)
Thanks for your reply Olivier.
I think that actually most (or at least a lot) of what people have to be careful of in communication is neither outright incompetence nor outright deception, but rather negligence. For instance in the informant in the story says that X tree is an apple tree, she might just be saying that without being really sure (it's something she heard, say), and with no intention of deceiving you. She just doesn't care much whether it's true or not. That might not be a sign of incompetence from her point of view, if she has no intention of going to that tree anyway. But if she gives you this information, she's being negligent in a way (especially if she fails to specify that she's not sure at all). In such a case, it makes sense to 'punish' the informant by trusting her less: she might not learn how to get better information (ie become more competent), but she'll learn to be more careful when transmitting it. If it is true that such situations arise pretty often, then 'punishment' would be quite a powerful way to insure the stability of communication.
Thom Scott-Phillips 24 June 2015 (12:12)
I am of course delighted that Olivier chose to organise a book club around SOM, and I would like to thank him here for the work he has put in to make this happen. We are just a few days into it, and it is already abundantly clear to me that this format is sure to advance discussion in several important ways. Olivier’s own contribution is a perfect example of this. These advances would not be occurring if not for Olivier’s efforts.
Olivier summarises very well my discussion of the evolutionary stability of human communication. My main objective in these sections was to stress that evolutionary stability is explained in a really rather simple way, once the underlying theory is properly understood (it has too often not been properly understood in the past). In short: human communication, or at least the overwhelming majority of it, is kept stable by reputation.
Olivier’s comments raise, first, a question about a terminological detail of this claim, and second, a collection of important tangential questions about how such a system could have emerged in the first place. Let me comment, more briefly than I would like, on these two issues in turn.
I argue in SOM that conspicuous consumption is not a handicap, since it does not involve differential costs. Olivier disputes this. The costs of conspicuous consumption are not differential in absolute terms, but they are, he points out, differential in marginal terms. The question, then, is whether the costs involved in signal production should be treated in absolute or marginal terms. The answer to this question will come from the modelling literature. Alan Grafen’s original model of the handicap principle, which lent a great deal of credibility to Amotz Zahavi’s propoals, certainly did conclude that marginal costs could stabilise costly communication. The literature has however moved on considerably since then. Olivier’s arguments have therefore encouraged me to revisit some key papers in this area, with this issue, and Olivier’s related comments about deer calls, in mind. Doing this, I see that the matter is not straightforward, and needs further consideration. I can right now only promise to report back in due course.
Olivier’s questions about the emergence of stable human communication are nicely summarised in his response to Hugo, above: “I raised four problems for Thom's account. It has to explain (1) how mutualism arose, (2) how people tell deceiving informants from incompetent ones, (3) how people know that their informants are more knowledgeable than they themselves are, and (4) how knowledge of deception spreads without communication when opportunities for eavesdropping are limited”. This are all good questions, to which (again) I do not have good answers at present. In this case, I think these questions amount almost to a manifesto for an original modelling project, aimed at identifying the range of parameters under which a mass communication system kept stable by reputation could emerge. Done well and comprehensively, a project of this sort should be able to address Hugo’s questions about the relative importance of the four problems. It should also tell us if Olivier’s suggestion, that public reputation could play an important role, is correct. Certainly, this seems as plausible to me as any speculation I can offer right now. I am slightly saddened that I have little to add to it at present, but I think this is for the best: for me to make additional speculations of any substance would, I think, be little more than second-guessing the results of the project outlined above.